In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:

Reviewed by:
  • A Free Will: Origins of the Notion in Ancient Thought by Michael Frede
  • Susan Sauvé Meyer
Michael Frede . A Free Will: Origins of the Notion in Ancient Thought. Sather Classical Lectures, 68. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 2011. Pp. xiv, 206. $60.00 (hb.). ISBN 978-0-520-26848-7; $29.95 (pb.) ISBN 978-0-520-27266-8.

In these posthumously published Sather Lectures, delivered at Berkeley in 1997-98 and edited by A. A. Long after the author's untimely death in 2007, Frede contests the assumption, common among philosophers today, that free will is an "ordinary" human notion independent of substantive theoretical commitments. But neither is it a distinctively Christian notion that first emerges in the works of Augustine, marking a radical break with pagan antiquity—a proposal made popular by Albrecht Dihle in his own Sather lectures (The Theory of the Will in Classical Antiquity, 1982). One of Frede's larger points is that a proper appreciation of pagan philosophy in late antiquity reveals its great continuities with early Christian thought. While Christianity is responsible for the widespread dissemination of the notion of free will, Frede argues, the notion itself originates in the philosophy of the Stoic Epictetus (55-135 c.e.). It gets absorbed into late Platonism along with other Stoic doctrines, whence it is transmitted to early Christian writers like Origen and Augustine in the third and fourth centuries.

There is no notion of a will, let alone a free will, in thinkers before the Stoics, Frede argues, for it is only with the Stoic doctrine that all human actions are the result of assent (συγκατάθεσις) that we encounter the notion of a will: that is, a power of choice or decision whose activity is a mental event that precedes all our actions. Later Peripatetics and Platonists, who have absorbed into their psychology of action the Stoic doctrine of assent, may also be credited with a notion of the will. Such a notion, Frede stresses, is not thereby a notion of a free will, even if combined with the assumption that our actions are "up to us" (ἐφ᾿ ἡμῖν), a phrase often wrongly translated "free," but that in fact invokes the quite distinct notions of responsibility and control. (His very useful further discussion, "The ἐφ᾿ ἡμῖν in ancient philosophy," Φιλοσοφία 37 [2007] 110-23, is unfortunately omitted from the bibliography.) Frede masterfully tracks the disagreements and developing positions of Platonists, Stoics, and Peripatetics about the nature of the ἐφ᾿ ἡμῖν, and its shifting relations to the ἑκούσιον, the αὐτεξούσιον, αὐτοπραγία, and ἐλευθερία, but it is specifically ἐλευθερία that Frede has in mind as the "freedom" of the will. Thus, he identifies Epictetus' invocation of a προαίρεσις that is ἐλευθέρα as the first occurrence of the notion of a free will (Diss. 1.4.18). [End Page 535]

Frede traces the different uses to which this notion is put by Alexander of Aphrodisias, Origen, Plotinus, and Augustine. He concludes that the notion of a free will is construed consistently across all these authors in its original Stoic sense: that is, as the ability to make correct choices in pursuit of a good life. To have freedom of the will thus requires that one not be forced to make choices incompatible with living well or be prevented from choosing correctly. It does not require an unconditioned "sheer act of will" undetermined by antecedent conditions—a notion that, in many circles today, has usurped the mantle of "freedom of the will" (and is the conception whose origin Dihle finds in Augustine). This is neither Augustine's nor Origen's notion of a free act of will, according to Frede. Nor is it that of Plotinus, who attributes such freedom only to God but not to human souls. The only ancient proponent of such a view, he finds, is the Peripatetic Alexander of Aphrodisias, whose position is driven by a "hopelessly misguided" picture of merit and desert that is not to be found in Aristotle himself.

Although Frede describes his project as a "historical" inquiry, he brings to bear on his material an acute philosophical intelligence. His exposition is compressed, sometimes breathtakingly astute, and occasionally inscrutable. The notes supplied by Long, with occasional supplements by the late Robert...

pdf

Share