In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:

Reviewed by:
  • Reading History Sideways: The Fallacy and Enduring Impact of the Developmental Paradigm on Family Life
  • Etienne van de Walle
Reading History Sideways: The Fallacy and Enduring Impact of the Developmental Paradigm on Family Life. By Arland Thornton (Chicago, University of Chicago Press, 2005) 312 pp. $29.95

The fallacy-inducing methodology of "reading history sideways" consists of taking contemporaneous evidence about other societies to infer past characteristics of our own. Typically, Thornton argues, social scientists of the eighteenth or nineteenth centuries (what he calls the 1700s and the 1800s) imagined that the past family structures of "modern" northwestern Europe could be investigated by looking at "traditional" societies outside of the region, for example in America, Africa, or Australia. Inversely, they thought that they could foretell the future state of "primitive" societies by assuming "development" would follow a predictable trajectory. Inferring temporal sequences from cross-sectional data assumed that "change is uniform, natural, necessary and directional"—what the author calls the developmental paradigm.

But this notion of steps on an inescapable ladder of development turned out to be a self-fulfilling prophesy, as it was vigorously promoted by powerful Western nations and widely adopted by societies that were seduced by the trappings of "westernization." Thornton calls "development idealism" the preconception that societal development produces change from non-Western family systems to those of Northwest Europe. He restricts his analysis to changes in family life, and identifies four propositions of development idealism: Modern society is good and attainable; the modern family is good and attainable; the modern family is a cause as well as an effect of a modern society; and individuals have the right to be free and equal, with social relationship being based on consent. [End Page 103] These propositions—together with other forces such as mass education, industrialization, urbanization, and the development of technology—have contributed to modifying family life, including marriage, fertility, and patterns of residence.

The argument is provocative, systematic, and cogent. As one of the citations on the blurb says, Reading History Sideways is an intellectual feast. The author introduces occasional sophisms, however, to make the argument more elegant. The book indicts many of the social theories obtained from sideways reading in the textbooks of demography and family sociology, and much of the conventional terminology of social science. Take for instance an often-cited sentence defining the demographic transition, which the writer granted was "neither subtle nor precise," but "described a central preoccupation of modern demography": "In traditional societies, fertility and mortality are high. In modern societies, fertility and mortality are low. In between, there is demographic transition."1 Thornton would condemn the use of the words traditional, modern, and transition, because they imply necessary stages in the development of society; the word "transition," in particular, suggests that changes are irreversible. But one objection to his point is that "traditional" and "modern" are convenient shorthands that can be replaced only by lengthy circumlocutions. He is correct in attacking the notion that specific social changes are necessary. Belief in their irreversibility, however, as in the case of fertility and mortality decline or technical progress in general, is less controversial.

The method of reading history sideways may not have been as dominant among the founding fathers of social science as the author claims. The evidence that he presents is problematical, because the references lack specificity. Footnotes cite the entire work of multiple authors as authorities about an often trivial point, without reference to a particular passage. See, for example, a mention of polygyny that "drew widespread attention and was judged by one observer to be so terrible that no woman would enter it voluntarily" (56) The footnote cites nine authors, including entire works of Friedrich Hegel, David Hume, Adam Smith, Michel de Montaigne, and Montesquieu (the latter two authors, at least, adopted nonjudgmental attitudes toward polygyny) without identifying the said "one observer" or even specifying on which of the many thousands of reference pages polygyny is mentioned. Many authors of the past used foreign social systems not as images of their own societies in an earlier time but as alternative models of society. Thomas Malthus or Smith, for example, did not picture China at a lower...

pdf

Share