Johns Hopkins University Press
  • Narrative Formulation RevisitedOn Seeing the Person in Mental Health Recovery

The use of narrative in mental health contexts models consciousness as something necessarily embodied, as already part of the world, in an inherently value-laden and perspectival way. As such narrative presents a powerful tool for critical reassessment and reevaluation of preconceived ideas in relating to difficult concepts in clinical interactions.

Narrative structures can reveal psychological differences between persons in a way that matters for the provision of effective treatment and management. As emphasized by Solomon (2015), narrative reasoning is also motivated by distinctly first-personal concerns that are operative in the practitioner–client relationship. I maintain that the dynamics of that interpersonal relationship are part and parcel of what it means to address the patient's needs to be seen as a person in humanistic empathetic care—without thereby reducing truth to an individual person's perspective to encourage positive transformation.1

The notion of empowering narratives to encourage positive change is a core concept behind the emphasis on the critical role of empathy in explaining human development and psychoanalytic change within the self-psychology tradition but is also key to recovery-based models of the significance of person-centered quality of life in medicine more generally. This is defined in mental health as recovering a good quality of life as determined by the values of (by what matters or is important to) the individual concerned (Allott, Loganathan, & Fulford, 2002; Fulford, 1989, 2004; Fulford, Peile, & Carroll, 2012). The importance of strengths in this regard was reflected for example in the UK government program on values-based mental health assessment. The 3 Keys program, as it was called (National Institute for Mental Health in England, NIMHE, and the Care Services Improvement Partnership, 20082) identified three shared 'keys' to good practice in mental health assessment: three things that were identified in a wide-ranging consultation as being important alike by health professionals of all kinds and by 'service users' thus understood as patients and carers (Fulford, Duhig, Hankin, Hicks, & Keeble, 2015a; Fulford, Dewey, & King, 2015b). The third of these keys was defined in [End Page 7] the subsequently published Good Practice Guidance, as "a person-centred focus that builds on the strengths, resiliencies and aspirations of the individual service user as well as identifying his or her needs and challenges" (NIMHE, 2008: 6); and the guidance included a number of real-life case examples of best recovery practice reflecting this aspect of mental health care (Slade et al., 2014).

What my (Bergqvist, 2018, 2020, 2022, forthcoming) account adds to this claim is that while such choices are revelatory or expressive of a distinctly first-personal stance, they do not constitute or determine selfhood and self-interpretation in a fixed way. Moreover, the reason is that one can also adopt a second-personal stance on one's own experience and address oneself, where the relationship between the first- and the second-personal narrative perspective on experience and self-understanding is itself a dynamic and open-ended evaluative process.

Anna Bergqvist

Anna Bergqvist is Reader in Philosophy at Manchester Metropolitan University since 2021, and has been Postgraduate Research Coordinator and AHRC North West Doctoral Pathway Consortium Lead for Philosophy since 2020. I was elected to a Visiting Fellowship at St Catherine's College University of Oxford for Michaelmas Term 2021. Her service to the profession out with the University includes acting as Secretary of the World Psychiatric Association (WPA) Section for Philosophy & Humanities in Psychiatry (October 2020 – present), Executive Committee Member of the Royal College of Psychiatry (RCPsych) SIG in Philosophy (February 2020 – present) and External Examiner, University of Liverpool (November 2019 – present, 4-year tenure). She is also Director of the Values-based Theory Network at St Catherine's Collaborating Centre for Values-based Practice at the University of Oxford, and Member of its Whiteness and Race Equality Network. Her approach to philosophy bridges the disciplines of moral philosophy, moral psychology and philosophy of psychiatry to improve lives through her reputable expertise in moral perception and co-production as a mechanism for change.

Notes

1. Here I side with Goldie (2012) and Solomon (2015), who warn against confusing the notion of autographical narrative (clinical or otherwise) with its intentional object.

2. A copy of the full report is available at valuesbasedpractice.org/More about VBP/Fulltext downloads.

References

Allott, P., Loganathan, L., & Fulford, K. W. M. (2002). Discovering hope for recovery. Innovation in Community Mental Health: International Perspectives. Canadian Journal of Community Mental Health, 21 (2), 13–33.
Bergqvist, A. (2018). Moral perception, thick concepts and perspectivalism. In A. Bergqvist & R. Cowan (Eds.), Evaluative perception. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press: 258–281.
Bergqvist, A. (2020). Narrative understanding, value and diagnosis: A particularist account of clinical formulations and shared decision-making in mental health. Philosophy, Psychology, & Psychiatry, 27 (2) 149–167.
Bergqvist, A. (2022). Psychiatric ethics. In S. Caprioglio Panizza & M. Hopwood (Eds.), The Murdochian mind. London: Routledge.
Bergqvist, A. (forthcoming). The phenomenology of mutual trust in psychotherapy: A relational account of meaning-making in recovery. In F. Brencio (Ed.), Phenomenology, neuroscience and clinical practices.
Bergqvist, A., Crepaz-Keay, D., & Bhui, K. (forthcoming). The Oxford handbook of philosophy and public mental health: Emerging theories, converging practice. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.
Fulford, K.W.M. (1989/1995/1999). Moral theory and medical practice. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Fulford, K. W. M. (2004). Ten principles of values-based medicine. In J. Radden (Ed.), The philosophy of psychiatry: A companion. New York: Oxford University Press; 205–234.
Fulford, K. W. M., Peile, E., & Carroll, H. (2012). Essential values-based practice: Clinical stories linking science with people. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Fulford, K. W. M., Duhig, L., Hankin, J., Hicks, J., & Keeble, J. (2015) Values-based assessment in mental health: The 3 keys to a shared approach between service users and service providers. In J. Z. Sadler, W. van Staden, & K. W. M. Fulford (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of psychiatric ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press
Fulford, K.W.M., Dewey, S., & King, M. (2015b). Values-based Involuntary Seclusion and Treatment: Value Pluralism and the UK's Mental Health Act 2007. In J. Z. Sadler, W. van Staden, & K. W. M. Fulford (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of psychiatric ethics. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.
Goldie, P. (2012). The mess inside: Narrative, emotion and the mind. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.
National Institute for Mental Health in England (NIMHE) and the Care Services Improvement Partnership. (2008). 3 Keys to a shared approach in mental health assessment. London: Department of Health. Available: http://valuesbasedpractice.org/ More about VBP/Full text downloads.
Slade, M., Amering, M., Farkas, M., Hamilton, B., O'Hagan, M., Panther, G., … Whitley, R. (2014). Uses and abuses of recovery: Implementing recovery-oriented practices in mental health systems. World Psychiatry, 13, 12–20.
Solomon, M. (2015). Making Medical Knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Share