In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:

Reviewed by:
  • Literature After Euclid: The Geometric Imagination in the Long Scottish Enlightenment by Matthew Wickman
  • Robert Irvine
Literature After Euclid: The Geometric Imagination in the Long Scottish Enlightenment. By Matthew Wickman. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 2016. ISBN 9780812247954. 352pp. hbk. £45.

This is a work of great erudition, setting Scottish literary history from The Seasons to MacDiarmid within the intellectual history of this period. It makes a very interesting and original claim: that literary innovation in the eighteenth and early nineteenth centuries can be understood in terms of the adoption and distortion of contemporary mathematical ideas, and geometrical ideas in particular. However, it does not construct an argument which uses that erudition to justify that claim. The starting point for this book seems to be the connection sometimes made between modernist art and the non-Euclidean geometries of the nineteenth century, combined with Thomas Reid’s apparent anticipation of those geometries in a passage of the Inquiry (1764). But Wickman coins the phrase ‘late Euclidean’, not to name a type of geometry, or a period in the history of mathematics, but to indicate ‘the deployment of a language of classically conceived nature to strange new ends’ and ‘a literature imagined, at once, in the manner of and as a successor to Euclidian norms’ (p. 5). The Introduction, and chapters 1 and 2, on the Scottish Enlightenment and Scott respectively, attempt to connect geometry to literary texts but can only do so through wordplay, free association and false logic. The following three chapters, on the picturesque, Burns, and Thomson, are often stimulating and insightful, but precisely to the extent that they abandon the attempt to frame their subject matter in terms of the ‘late Euclidean’.

In the early chapters, ‘geometry’ is often a place-holder for something more general: the abstract as opposed to the concrete, space as opposed to time, the immanent as opposed to the mediated, and so on. But these terms can only be translated back into ‘geometry’ by some striking departures from logic. For example, the plays of Joanna Baillie involve an element of abstraction; geometry is an abstract science; therefore, Baillie’s plays reveal a mind ‘that remained evocatively Euclidean’ (p. 3). In Reid, the ‘geometry of visibles’ is a ‘natural language’ (its signified is the ‘geometry of tangibles’), to be distinguished from ‘artificial language’ (compared by Reid, in contrast, to algebra). That is correct; but Wickman then has to misread Hugh Blair’s distinction, in Lectures XIV, between ‘Figures of Words’ (‘Tropes’) and ‘Figures of Thought’ (a distinction Blair immediately identifies as ‘of no [End Page 157] great use’ nor ‘always very clear’) as a distinction between ‘artificial’ and ‘natural’ language in Reid’s sense (they are equally ‘natural’ for Blair) so that ‘tropes, essentially, are algebraic, while figures are geometric’. Another misreading, of Macpherson’s ‘Dissertation’, then claims Gaelic as a ‘natural language’, again, it appears, in Reid’s sense, to conclude that the aesthetic of Ossian ‘was thus modelled on a geometric analogy – which is to say, on the (geometric) ideal of “evidence”’ (p. 33).

Certainly, these chapters also refer to the actual practice of geometry in the specific context of Scotland in the eighteenth and early nineteenth centuries, and especially the work of Colin Maclaurin and Robert Simson. But there is no sustained discussion of any of the Scottish mathematical texts that are cited (Simson’s career gets some attention in chapter 4). Adelene Buckland has written very interestingly of Scott’s friendship with the mathematician John Playfair in Novel Science (2013), but there is nothing here of that sort of specificity. Scott’s novels reflect on their own representational procedures; the non-Euclidean geometries that emerge at around the same time as Scott’s novels describe straight lines that bend around on themselves (because inscribed on a sphere); therefore, Scott’s narrative practice anticipates a ‘non-Euclidean poetics’. The organisation of the reader’s sympathies by the narrative perspective of Waverley, on the other hand, can be expressed as an algebraic formula; algebra, we must remember, is different from geometry; therefore, Scott’s novels combine a geometric poetics with an algebraic epistemology, sharing the syncretic character’ of ‘mathematics in...

pdf

Share