In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:

Reviewed by:
  • Mechanisms: New Media and the Forensic Imagination
  • Jan Baetens (bio)
Mechanisms: New Media and the Forensic Imagination by Matthew G. Kirschenbaum. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, U.S.A., 2008. 316 pp., illus. Trade. ISBN 10: 0-262-11311-2; ISBN 13: 978-0-262-11311-3.

In reflection on new media, this book is undoubtedly a watershed publication. Its basic stance is that electronic writing can only be understood if we accept it as a real form of writing, that is, of material inscriptions on material surfaces, and therefore to leave behind many of the myths that surround digital culture. This grammatological stance, which the author borrows as much from Jacques Derrida (whose Archive Fever is one of the major sources of inspiration of this book) as from Friedrich Kittler (whom Kirschenbaum criticizes however quite vividly for his often sweeping over generalizations), goes against the grain of what many first-generation thinkers on digital writing in new media environments had too easily taken for granted, namely the idea that electronic writing was evanescent, ephemeral, multi-authored (if not authorless), permanently shifting, freed from all kinds of fixed form, and so on.

Against these myths, Kirschenbaum opens his book with two stunning examples (which at the end of this work the reader will no longer interpret as "stunning" but as "perfectly normal"): first the impossibility of realizing the announced self-destruction of a piece of e-literature (William Gibson's Agrippa); second, the possibility of recovering data from the hard disks physically damaged in the 9/11 attacks (various companies had by then already developed the necessary software to restore the content of the computers' black boxes). The lessons that can be drawn from these two examples are then extended by the author to a new theory of electronic writing, which puts a great emphasis on the materiality of both the process and the product: inscription, storage, retrieval and transmission are the master words of a renewed form of philology, no longer bound to the a prior is of the old discipline, but updated and adapted to what writing and reading have become in the digital age (in this regard, Kirschenbaum continues the groundbreaking work launched by scholars such as Jerome McGann, although in a slightly different direction).

What makes Kirschenbaum's work so thrilling and innovative is, however, not only the demonstration that electronic writing is also a way of writing, even if the computer is a machine meant to withdraw its own material operations from our attention (its technology is a typical "black box" technology, and it is very refreshing to notice that Kirschenbaum's view of this type of technology helps to avoid Vilém Flusser's influential attacks in his amply read and discussed Towards a Philosophy of Photography). At least as important is the humanist viewpoint defended by the author, whom some may know as a very careful reader of Foucault. In this regard, a key role is played by the notion of "forensics," a branch of criminology known as "trace evidence," whose inventor, the French investigator Edmond Locard, coined the "exchange principle" (which one can freely paraphrase as: "every contact leaves a trace"). In his book, Kirschenbaum uses forensics as a tool to think of electronic writing as a chain of contacts that are never materially lost, while at the same time insisting on the fact that it is much more than just a sequencing of inscriptions on a hard disk (or on other types of surfaces, although the hard disk has now become the dominant form).

On the one hand, he argues that forensics breeds a new type of attention and imagination, both similar to and different from the reading of clues in general. What defines the specificity of forensic imagination in the case of digital writing is the split between forensic and formal materiality, the former having to do with the "product" (which inscriptions have been made, which marks can be read?), the latter, with the "process" (how are these inscriptions and marks being transferred from one surface to another?). From a semiotic point of view, inspired by Nelson Goodman, Kirschenbaum calls the forensic materiality "autographical" (no two marks are identical...

pdf

Share