In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:

Reviewed by:
  • Infinitesimal Differences: Controversies between Leibniz and his Contemporaries
  • Françoise Monnoyeur-Broitman
Ursula Goldenbaum and Douglas Jesseph, editors. Infinitesimal Differences: Controversies between Leibniz and his Contemporaries. Berlin-New York: Walter de Gruyter, 2008. Pp. vi + 327. Cloth, $109.00.

Leibniz is well known for his formulation of the infinitesimal calculus. Nevertheless, the nature and logic of his discovery are seldom questioned: does it belong more to mathematics or metaphysics, and how is it connected to his physics? This book, composed of fourteen essays, investigates the nature and foundation of the calculus, its relationship to the physics of force and principle of continuity, and its overall method and metaphysics. The Leibnizian calculus is presented in its origin and context together with its main contributors: Archimedes, Cavalieri, Wallis, Hobbes, Pascal, Huygens, Bernoulli, and Nieuwentijt.

Many of us know and probably have used the Leibnizian formula: to calculate the area under a curve; this book considers the origin, nature, method, and metaphysics of this formula. The most fascinating question discussed in it is the fiction introduced to define the infinitesimal calculation: in his mature period, Leibniz himself referred to his calculus as “a well-founded fiction.” We learn that he gradually gave up the idea of an actual infinite in favor of describing infinitely small quantities. As a result, the quantities became fictive and finite or indefinite instead of real and infinite, and the process of calculation shifted towards mathematics rather than metaphysics.

In the first essay, Richard Arthur compares the calculus of Leibniz and Newton and demonstrates how it was based for both on the development of continuously varying quantity. He also shows how the understanding of this quantity derived from the Archimedean axiom that excludes the existence of actual infinite quantity. Ursula Goldenbaum next demonstrates how Hobbes, with his conatus considered as point and instant, had a direct impact on the Leibnizian conception of continuity; to confirm her interpretation, she includes at the end of her article the “Marginalia or Leibniz comments” on Hobbes. Samuel Levey establishes a connection between the notion of the infinitesimal as a “well-founded fiction” and the law of continuity, arguing that the law of continuity, understood as an extension of Archimedes’ principle, gives a finite foundation to the infinitesimal calculation. O. Bradley Bassler discusses the idea of the differential in terms of infinitely small quantities and the use of proportions between infinitely small and finite quantities in order to measure [End Page 527] the infinitely small; here, differentials are also presented as fictions. Fritz Nagel discusses the methodological sophistication of the calculus and its opponents. His main questions concern the different grades of infinity, quantities regarded as zero, and the infinitesimal as a fiction that can be calculated. Douglas Jesseph considers the reality of the infinitesimal and the “well-founded fiction,” showing how Leibniz methodically constructs infinitesimal quantities without reality by returning to Hobbes’ notion of conatus. Hobbes is, for Jesseph, the initiator of these infinitely small quantities without existence.

A second group of essays examines the connection between algebra and geometry in the calculus. Philip Beeley demonstrates how John Wallis, on the path of Cavalieri’s method of the indivisibles, found a way to transform geometric problems into sums of arithmetic sequences. Siegmund Probst expresses the different phases in the discovery of the Leibnizian method. He mentions that Leibniz coined the term ‘infinitesimal’ in 1673, and points out that he did not need the method of indivisibles to find a curve from its given arc, but only a series expansion using differences of higher order. Emily Grosholz looks at how, thanks to his algebraic and geometrical notations of curves, Leibniz could formulate the equation of his infinitesimal calculus. According to Grosholz, Leibniz exploits the ambiguity of notations in order to express the geometrical and dynamical aspect of the calculus. Herbert Breger underlines the novelty and abstract nature of Leibniz’s new method of calculation, showing how the theory of infinitesimals became an algebraic calculus independent of geometry.

A final group of articles studies the relationship between the calculus and Leibniz’s physics. François Duchesneau shows how the differential and integral calculus provided a model for the integrative laws of Leibniz’s...

pdf

Share