In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:

DOI: 10.7330/9780874219364.c001 1 Th e M e a n i n g o f M e a n i n g What we believe about words influences the ways in which we live our lives, what we think and say and do. Notice that I’m not referring to our uses of language: it’s obvious that speaking, writing, listening, and reading have consequences for our lives. What I’m suggesting is rather less apparent: attitudes we have, assumptions we make, beliefs we hold, mostly tacit and unexamined, about what language can do for us, how language works, its connections to the world, the reliability of meaning , the truth-value of different kinds of statements, all affect our lives just as much as, and perhaps even more deeply than, our actual usage. Anthropologist and linguist Edward Sapir, known for his insights into the relativity of representation across languages, argued the error of supposing that “one adjusts to reality without the use of language” and insisted that the “real” world is “to a large extent unconsciously built up on the language habits” of different groups of people. No two languages , he writes, “are ever sufficiently similar to be considered as representing the same social reality” (Sapir 1964, 69). Sapir’s observations in linguistics (the study of language) are pertinent also for rhetoric (the study of discourse). That is, what he argued regarding different assumptions about words and reality in different languages anticipates similar distinctions among the multiple, complexly interwoven discourses, or communication practices, that compose social experience in any one language—domestic discourses (the verbal routines of everyday life), religious discourses, scientific, legal, political, medical, artistic, educational , scholarly, and other discourses. These discourses are themselves different worlds of words, albeit within a single language, and they feature , some more self-consciously than others, not just distinct vocabularies , syntactic styles, and registers, but different views of what C. K. Ogden and I. A. Richards (1923) called “the meaning of meaning”—how things are named, what (if anything) is to be regarded as reliably “true,” what counts as “proof,” how the literal is distinguished from the figurative, who can speak authoritatively, what knowledge is and how it’s achieved, 2   C. H. Knoblauch and myriad other questions. In the most self-conscious of these discourses —religious, legal, or scholarly, for example—one commonly finds competing rhetorical theories vying for authority, with significant consequences attending the ebb and flow of alternative points of view. Ask a Catholic and an Anglican theologian about their contrasting views of the doctrine of transubstantiation, or two lawyers about the “intent” of the framers of the US Constitution, or two literary critics about their readings of “Young Goodman Brown,” and conflicts regarding not just meaning but also the meaning of meaning will be quickly apparent. Meaning and E veryday Li fe But let’s begin more simply with the familiar discourses of everyday life and consider the tacit rhetorical assumptions of a couple of ordinary Americans whom I will call, for ease of reference, George and Louise. Friday morning, George comes down to breakfast and the newspaper, observes while pouring milk on his cornflakes that the carton says “sell by September 15,” which was two days ago, and, fearing the milk may be spoiling, plays safe and empties the carton in the sink. He reads a front-page story on a bond proposal to fund new buildings in his local school district and accepts the objectivity of the report along with the display of evidence supporting the need for new taxes to pay for the borrowing. He’s unhappy, however, about Hispanic “aliens” driving up enrollment, and also with school programs that seem to put “multiculturalism ” ahead of learning English. Turning to the editorial page, he finds a piece on global warming to be mere opinion, unsubstantiated by facts, its author melodramatic, and decides to withhold judgment until dispassionate science quiets the noise of discordant voices. As for the ad on page 6 hawking “eye-catching cosmetics,” he recognizes the manipulative play of words, smirks briefly at the ad’s fictions of beauty and sexuality, which he knows were conjured for commercial advantage, and dismisses its claims. Reaching his office building later in the morning, he glances at the sign in the elevator warning not to exceed a limit of twelve occupants, takes it as an engineer’s appraisal, casually estimates the number of his fellow travelers, and rides confidently to his workplace. He spends part...

Share