In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:

two who’s a pragmatist Royce, Dewey, and Peirce at the Turn of the Century Doug Anderson  This essay grew out of conversations concerning the philosophical similarities among the early pragmatists, including Royce. Often their differences seem exaggerated and their shared beliefs overlooked, in large part because of contemporary pragmatists’ tendency to self-identify as Royceans , Jamesians, Deweyans, and Peirceans. These conversations led me to reread the early pragmatists, attending to the ways in which they influenced one another. [Pragmatism] is, so far, a house at war against itself concerning not inconsiderable questions; but perhaps this will not endanger its stability, and it certainly renders the discussions more interesting. Charles Peirce, The Nation 3 (1905): 233 I. Introduction Ultimately, it may not matter much who is or is not a pragmatist. There are some reasonable political motivations at any given time for {  } who’s a pragmatist  wanting or not wanting to be counted as among the pragmatists, depending on whether pragmatism is or is not in vogue. But if we ask how the question ‘‘who is a pragmatist?’’ was answered by Josiah Royce, Charles Peirce, and John Dewey in the early years of the twentieth century, we find some interesting answers that we can use to help sketch a picture of where their respective philosophical commitments lay. It is an interesting heuristic tool. Seeing how they answered the question helps us sharpen the boundaries and borders among their respective outlooks. The foci of my particular query are Royce’s, Dewey’s, and Peirce’s notions of a method of inquiry and their respective assessments of what Peirce called his ‘‘scholastic realism.’’ Here I follow Peirce, who in a 1905 letter to Mario Calderoni wrote, ‘‘Pragmaticism [the ‘‘first kind of pragmatism’’] is not a system of philosophy. It is only a method of thinking.’’ It is a method, he stated, that also ‘‘best comports’’ with his common sensism and, consequently , his scholastic realism (CP 8.206–08). And in 1904 Peirce similarly wrote to William James: ‘‘The most important consequence of it [pragmatism], by far . . . is that under the conception of reality we must abandon nominalism’’ (CP 8.258). My hunch is that though there are clear continuities among their views, Peirce explicitly marked out and developed a strong middle ground between Royce’s ‘‘absolute pragmatism’’ and Dewey’s ‘‘instrumentalism.’’ Holding this middle ground was important precisely because it allowed Peirce to capture a wider range of human experience and natural history than he believed was captured by Royce or Dewey in their more extreme moments. In his recent essay ‘‘Peirce’s Place in the Pragmatist Tradition,’’ Sami Pihlström maintains that there were many more affinities among the early pragmatists than is sometimes acknowledged. Here he follows in the tradition of John E. Smith, Max Fisch, and Stan Thayer, among others. I agree with Pihlström’s observation and thus begin by answering my own question with the claim that all of the above are pragmatists, and I would add to the mix without hesitation William James and F. C. S. Schiller. What is interesting to me is that [18.191.216.163] Project MUSE (2024-04-16 06:48 GMT)  doug anderson not all the early pragmatists answered in this fashion. I am not referring here to Peirce’s well-known renaming of his own position as ‘‘pragmaticism.’’ On the contrary, it appears that Peirce was more inclusive than his pragmatic kin. Royce, after first rejecting pragmatism as James and Peirce initially presented it, later commandeered it by transforming it into what he believed was its only workable form: absolute pragmatism. Dewey in turn traced the development of Royce’s thought, arguing that Royce, contrary to his claim, had never been a pragmatist. Royce initially attacked the pragmatic method in The Religious Aspect of Philosophy, where he argued that inquiry—the quest for truth and the avoidance of error—could not be conducted in the absence of an absolute judge. His argument there was a reduction to the condition of the possibility of error, and it was of a sort that Peirce would have classified as a priori. For Royce, ‘‘The conditions that determine the possibility of error must themselves be absolute truth,’’1 and the central condition he found was the actual presence of an ‘‘absolute judge’’ whose judgment was inclusive of all finite judgments. The ‘‘truth’’ he claimed to find was this: ‘‘All reality must be present to the Unity of the Infinite...

Share