Oxford University Press
Reviewed by:
Common Morality: Deciding What to Do. By Bernard Gert. Oxford University Press, 2004. 179 pages. $25.00

Common Morality fits into that special, useful genre of philosophical scholarship that lays out the comprehensive conditions for moral reasoning in a manner accessible to students and intelligent laymen. One of the reasons it reads so well is that it is the fourth restatement of Gert's descriptive account of morality, which he has been developing for the last forty years. (The first three were The Moral Rules: A New Rational Foundation for Morality, Harper & Row, 1970; Morality, A New Justification of the Moral Rules, Oxford, 1988; and most recently, Morality: Its Nature and Justification, Oxford, 1998). Not only is this printing the most succinct of the four, it addresses some important objections that ensued following the earlier renditions. [End Page 221]

Gert's thesis is that "common morality" is the best of all the available options for describing the reasoning system that we both would want to use and, in fact, implicitly do use when deliberating on what we ought, morally, to do. Gert argues that common morality both explains why there is so much cross-cultural widespread moral agreement as well as provides a method for separating the plurality of sensible solutions to quandaries, over which there is widespread disagreement, from the irrational ones. What distinguishes "common morality" from its alternatives is that its procedural constraints are based exclusively on noticeable universal features of human nature, like the human propensity to err, our capacity for reasoning, and our vulnerability, which together indicate both our insecurity and a way for us to become more secure than we are in the state of nature. In other words, Gert argues, common morality is the moral system that reflective, rational people would want to use because it protects us and everyone for whom we would hypothetically be concerned by calling attention directly to the purpose of morality: to guide behavior by shielding ourselves and each other from the harms from which all rational people would want to be free: death, physical pain, debility, enslavement, and the lack of pleasure (7). These protections are secured by ten clear rules to which abidance is not too onerous but whose effects are significantly beneficial to require of everyone (26–57). These rules are, in turn, supplemented by more costly and more beneficial moral ideals, encouraged but not required of moral agents, which can, from time to time, override the moral rules when the two come into conflict (22ff.).

In Part I Gert employs a "two-step" procedure for filtering out unjustified violations of the moral rules. The first stage involves making explicit the morally relevant facts in a particular quandary by asking a series of probing questions, for example, which rules are being violated? what harms will likely accrue from these violations? what are the intentions of the prospective violator? could such a violation ever be justified based on the particular relationship between the violator and the violated? One of Gert's major points in this book is that, surprisingly, most moral disagreements are based on disputes over these facts and not primarily over what we value—because human nature to a large degree already governs what we basically value. (Gert enumerates four exceptions to this claim on page 13.) Part I of the two-step procedure equips us with the capacity to present to ourselves a flowchart for determining at each stage of deliberation whether our proposed course of action is rational and/or moral. To this end Gert provides the reader with two useful algorithms for testing his or her own rational deliberation (151–152). The second stage in the two-step procedure involves polling moral agents to determine whether or not there is a consensus among them for estimating the consequences of allowing particular moral violations to stand (74ff.). Society may not consistently endorse the moral rules, but when it does not there will be pragmatic explanations for the exceptions.

Gert's system of identifying violations and then subsequently identifying which preventions of violations are less enforceable than others allows for a plurality of voices and solutions. To be sure while human nature indicates fairly clearly what constitutes pain and suffering, different people will rank different harms differently (91). For example, some people will rank some chronic [End Page 222] diseases to be harmful greater than death. Here, Gert points out that while common morality is limited—neither it nor any other moral system can resolve every controversial dispute—it can indicate the procedure, which has a chronological regularity each time it is applied for avoiding irrational discourse. In this sense Gert's account of morality makes explicit what is in his view already implicit: the presence of a distinctive grammar and system of language apropos to morality that enable conditions for sensible moral reasoning in the first place. Our desire to mitigate the conditions of human vulnerability, for example, cannot be denied any less by rational agents than the fact that the internal logic of sentences yields intelligible meanings can be denied by competent speakers. (15–17).

In Part II of Common Morality Gert sets out to justify the system he outlines in Part I. Why would all thoughtful, moral agents adopt the moral system that requires everyone categorically either to follow the moral rules of common morality or be justified in the context of their society for allowing the violations of these rules to stand? Here, Gert emphasizes the trait of impartiality in rational discourse and in doing so distinguishes himself from Hobbes and his contractarian descendents who seek only to justify morality to the rational egoist. For Gert, justification hangs on the conditional requirement that rational agents make judgments about a proposed course of action through exclusive reference to rationally required beliefs, namely the views held by all rational agents, which do not include, for example, religious, nationalistic, or tribal beliefs. Furthermore, Gert also restricts the domain of common morality to other moral agents about whom it is known that they are moral agents with all rationally required beliefs and knowledge (85). While it is never irrational to act morally, it can be rational to act immorally if there is an objective estimation, based on the facts, in which such can be accounted for consequentially (86ff.). Self-interest and morality can conflict with one another, and it can be rational to follow either; however, it can be irrational to act immorally, depending on the nature and degree of the harms that I, as an agent, stand to accrue in individual cases. This conclusion, though incomplete, is still comprehensive enough to rule out many superficially ambiguous courses of action as either irrational, immoral, or both.

Common Morality is not without its weaknesses, most of which, in spite of the author's claims to the contrary, are related to the grandiose ambition of the project contained in a mere 179 pages. At times Gert seems to assume that moral agreement is more widespread than it in fact is, in particular with respect to his faith in our prospects of reaching consensus about when violations of the moral rules are justified. But there are areas in which one might also take issue with the rules themselves. In particular, one might take issue with the stark threshold, Gert affirms, beyond which the obligatory rules give way to the recommended ideals, giving the impression that morally demanding altruistic behaviors, such as acts of heroism, are never required, a conclusion that moral heroes themselves often contest. Such a move precludes the possibility that that some "ideals" could be considered optional at one point in an agent's moral development but required down the road. The upshot of this hard and fast division is a moral theory that all but neglects virtue ethics and instead places its attention on the standard, "deontic" tendency, now held to be controversial, in which moral [End Page 223] judgments are based strictly on the performance or nonperformance of specific acts. Finally, religious studies scholars may be interested to know that Gert's view bluntly dismisses religion as irrelevant to ethics; not only does religious belief have no justificatory appeal in his view, it stands not in a mutual, but subsidiary, relation to morality (x). The idea that some universal truths may have different justifications for subscribers to different traditions at various local levels remains entirely unconsidered in this work.

Still, Common Morality is, overall, to be commended for its clarity, reattention to the moral facts, and inclusiveness of other major historical contributors to our understanding of ethics (Kant and Mill, in particular). Moreover, there is a refreshing honesty about Gert's style, which is no doubt connected to his denial that the moral rules, setting aside the issue of whether or not they are exhaustive of moral requirement altogether, will procure for the moral agent a single right answer for every possible moral situation.

Andrew Michael Flescher
California State University

Share